Minimal Group Agency

A Bio-Social Ontology

Authors

  • Joshua Rust Stetson University

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.25365/jso-2025-8918

Keywords:

group agency, enactivism, normativity, intentionality, moral responsibility, organicism, power, organizational closure

Abstract

When considering the type of agency that supports group activity, social ontologists often think of full-fledged moral and intentional agency. However, many organism-agents found in the biological sphere fail not only to be morally responsible but also would seem incapable of the rational guidance characteristic of intentional agency. This raises the possibility that some groups may qualify as minimal agents without necessarily qualifying as moral or intentional agents. In this paper, I review conditions for minimal agency as set forth by enactivists and draw from existing social ontological work to explore the extent to which these conditions might be satisfied by existing accounts of group agency. Although no account of group agency perfectly aligns with the enactivist conditions, I conclude that a suitably modified version of List and Pettit's account could.

References

Ancona, Deborah G et al. (2004). Managing for the Future: Organizational Behavior and Processes. 3rd. Mason, OH: Cengage Learning.

Anscombe, G E M (1958). “Modern Moral Philosophy”. Philosophy 33(124), pp. 1–19.

Bach, Kent (1978). “A Representational Theory of Action”. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 34(4), pp. 361–379. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/1059712309343819.

Barandiaran, Xabier, Marieke Rohde, and Ezequiel Di Paolo (2009). “Defining Agency: Individuality, Normativity, Asymmetry, and Spatio-Temporality in Action”. Adaptive Behavior 17(5). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/1059712309343819.

Barrett, Nathaniel F (2017). “The Normative Turn in Enactive Theory: An Examination of Its Roots and Implications”. Topoi 36(3), pp. 431–443. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9355-y.

Bickhard, Mark H (2019). “Dynamics Is Not Enough: An Interactivist Perspective”. Human Development 63(3–4), pp. 227–244. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1159/000503826.

Birch, Jonathan (2024). The Edge of Sentience: Risk and Precaution in Humans, Other Animals, and AI. Oxford / New York: Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/9780191966729.001.0001.

Bird, Alexander (2010). Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199227013.001.0001.

Björnsson, Gunnar and Kendy Hess (2017). “Corporate Crocodile Tears? On the Reactive Attitudes of Corporate Agents”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 94(2), pp. 273–298. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12260.

Bratman, Michael (2018). “Review: Kirk Ludwig, From Plural to Institutional Agency: Collective Action II”. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Published 2.8.2018. URL: https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/from-plural-to-institutional-agency-collective-action-ii/.

Bratman, Michael (2022). Shared and Institutional Agency: Toward a Planning Theory of Human Practical Organization. Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780197580899.001.0001.

Burman, Åsa (2023). Nonideal Social Ontology: The Power View. Oxford / New York: Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780197509579.001.0001.

Butlin, Patrick (2024). “Reinforcement Learning and Artificial Agency”. Mind & Language 39(1), pp. 22–38. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12458.

Crary, Alice (2011). “A Brilliant Perspective: Diamondian Ethics”. Philosophical Investigations 34(4), pp. 331–352. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9205.2011.01454.x.

Dennett, Daniel C (1995). Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. Allen Lane.

Di Paolo, Ezequiel (2010). “Overcoming Autopoiesis: An Enactive Detour on the Way from Life to Society”. In: Advanced Series in Management. Ed. by R Magalhães and R Sanchez. Vol. 6. Emerald Group Publishing Limited, pp. 43–68. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1108/S1877-6361(2009)0000006004.

Di Paolo, Ezequiel, Marieke Rohde, and Hanne De Jaegher (2010). “Horizons for the Enactive Mind: Values, Social Interaction, and Play”. In: Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science. Ed. by John Stewart, Olivier Gapenne, and Ezequiel A. Di Paolo. The MIT Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262014601.003.0003.

Di Paolo, Ezequiel, Thomas Buhrmann, and Xabier Barandiaran (2017). Sensorimotor Life: An Enactive Proposal. Oxford University Press.

Diamond, Cora (1991). “The Importance of Being Human”. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 29, pp. 35–62. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S135824610000744X.

Dworkin, Ronald (1986). Law’s Empire. Harvard University Press.

Elder-Vass, Dave (2007). “Luhmann and Emergentism: Competing Paradigms for Social Systems Theory?” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 37(4), pp. 408–432. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/0048393107307660.

Fard, Sahar Heydari (2024). “The Transformative Power of Social Movements”. Philosophy Compass 19(1). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12951.

Foot, Philippa (2003). Natural Goodness. Oxford: Clarendon Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/0198235089.001.0001.

Freund, Julia et al. (2013). “Emergence of Individuality in Genetically Identical Mice”. Science 340(6133), pp. 756–759. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1235294.

Gambarotto, Andrea (2023). “Teleology and Mechanism: A Dialectical Approach”. Synthese 201(5). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04137-y.

Gärtner, Klaus (1990). “A Third Component Causing Random Variability beside Environment and Genotype. A Reason for the Limited Success of a 30 Year Long Effort to Standardize Laboratory Animals?” Laboratory Animals 24(1), pp. 71–77. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1258/002367790780890347.

Gaus, Gerald (2021). The Open Society and Its Complexities. New York: Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190648978.001.0001.

Groff, Ruth (2011). “Getting Past Hume in the Philosophy of Social Science”. In: Causality in the Sciences. Ed. by Phyllis McKay Illari, Federica Russo, and Jon Williamson. Oxford University Press, pp. 296–316. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199574131.003.0014.

Groff, Ruth (2021). “Conceptualizing Causal Powers: Activity, Capacity, Essence, Necessitation”. Synthese 199(3), pp. 9881–9896. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03229-x.

Haslanger, Sally (2024a). “A Naturalistic Approach to Social Ontology”. Journal of Social Ontology 10(3), pp. 24–30. DOI: https://doi.org/10.25365/jso-2024-9029.

Haslanger, Sally (2024b). “Social Systems and the Reproduction of Injustice.” (Keynote Presentation), Social Ontology 2024, July 22–25, 2024, Duke University. Durham.

Heclo, Hugh (2011). On Thinking Institutionally. Oxford University Press.

Hindriks, Frank (2012). “But Where Is the University?” Dialectica 66(1), pp. 93–113. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1746-8361.2012.01289.x.

Hordijk, Wim, Mike Steel, and Stuart Kauffman (2013). “The Origin of Life, Evolution, and Functional Organization”. In: Evolutionary Biology: Exobiology and Evolutionary Mechanisms. Ed. by Pierre Pontarotti. Berlin / Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 49–60. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-38212-3_4.

Hornsby, Jennifer (1980). Actions. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Hull, David (1976). “Are Species Really Individuals?” Systematic Biology 25(2), pp. 174–191. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2412744.

Hull, David (1994). “Individual”. In: Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Ed. by Evelyn Fox Keller and Elisabeth A. Lloyd. Harvard University Press, pp. 181–187.

Hurley, Susan (2005). “Rational Agency, Cooperation and Mind-Reading”. In: Teamwork. Ed. by Natalie Gold. London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 200–215. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230523203_10.

Hutto, Daniel D and Erik Myin (2012). Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds without Content. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262018548.001.0001.

Ingold, Tim and Gisli Palsson (2013). Biosocial Becomings: Integrating Social and Biological Anthropology. Ed. by Ingold, Tim, and Gisli Palsson. Cambridge University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139198394.

Jonas, Hans (1966). The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology. Chicago, Ill: Northwestern University Press.

Kauffman, S A (1986). “Autocatalytic Sets of Proteins”. Journal of Theoretical Biology 119(1), pp. 1–24. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/s0022-5193(86)80047-9.

Kreps, David (2011). “Political Economy of Institutions and Decisions”. In: Perspectives on Positive Political Economy. Ed. by James E. Alt and Kenneth A. Shepsle. Cambridge University Press, pp. 90–143. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511571657.006.

Lawson, Tony (2013). “Emergence and Social Causation”. In: Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism. Ed. by John Greco and Ruth Groff. New York: Routledge. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203075609.

Levin, Michael and Daniel C Dennett (2020). “Cognition All the Way Down”. Aeon. URL: https://aeon.co/essays/how-to-understand-cells-tissues-and-organisms-as-agents-with-agendas.

Lewejohann, Lars, Benjamin Zipser, and Norbert Sachser (2011). “‘Personality’ in Laboratory Mice Used for Biomedical Research: A Way of Understanding Variability?” Developmental Psychobiology 53(6), pp. 624–630. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1002/dev.20553.

List, Christian (2004). “A Model of Path-Dependence in Decisions over Multiple Propositions”. The American Political Science Review 98(3), pp. 495–513. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055404001303.

List, Christian and Philip Pettit (2011). Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199591565.001.0001.

Ludwig, Kirk (2017). From Plural to Institutional Agency: Collective Action II. Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198789994.001.0001.

Maiese, Michelle and Robert Hanna (2019). The Mind-Body Politic. Palgrave Macmillan. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-19546-5.

McDowell, John (1996). Mind and World: With a New Introduction by the Author. 2nd. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

McLaughlin, Peter (2000). What Functions Explain: Functional Explanation and Self-Reproducing Systems. Cambridge University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498510.

Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (2010). Phenomenology of Perception. Translated by Donald Landes. London: Routledge. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203720714.

Messinger, Sheldon L (1955). “Organizational Transformation: A Case Study of a Declining Social Movement”. American Sociological Review 20(1), pp. 3–10. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2088192.

Midgley, Mary (1992). “Philosophical Plumbing”. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 33, pp. 139–151. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/s1358246100002319.

Millikan, R G (1989). “In Defense of Proper Functions”. Philosophy of Science 56(2), pp. 288–302. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1086/289488.

Moll, Henrike and Michael Tomasello (1480). “Cooperation and Human Cognition: The Vygotskian Intelligence Hypothesis”. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 362(1480), pp. 639–648. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2006.2000.

Molnar, George (1999). “Are Dispositions Reducible?” Philosophical Quarterly 49(194), pp. 1–17. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9213.00125.

Molnar, George (2003). Powers: A Study in Metaphysics. Ed. by Stephen Mumford. New York: Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199204175.001.0001.

Molter, Dan (2017). “On Mushroom Individuality”. Philosophy of Science 84(5), pp. 1117–1127. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1086/694011.

Murdoch, Iris (2001). The Sovereignty of Good. 2nd. London: Routledge.

Neander, K (1991). “Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst’s Defense”. Philosophy of Science 58(2), pp. 168–184. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1086/289610.

Novick, Aaron and Milton Weiner (1957). “Enzyme Induction as an All-Or-None Phenomenon”. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 43(7), pp. 553–566. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.43.7.553.

Lovejoy, Arthur O (1941). “The Meaning of Romanticism for the Historian of Ideas”. Journal of the History of Ideas 2(3), pp. 257–278. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2707131.

Papadopoulos, Dennis (2023). “Shared Intentionality in Nonhuman Great Apes: A Normative Model”. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 14(4), pp. 1125–1145. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-021-00594-x.

Paul, L A (2015). Transformative Experience. Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198717959.001.0001.

Peirce, Charles Sanders (1932). Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce: Volume II Elements of Logic. Harvard University Press.

Peirce, Charles Sanders (1992). The Essential Peirce, Volume 1: Selected Philosophical Writings? (1867–1893). Indiana University Press.

Petersson, Björn (2007). “Collectivity and Circularity”. The Journal of Philosophy 104(3), pp. 138–156. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110327175.145.

Pradeu, Thomas (2011). The Limits of the Self: Immunology and Biological Identity. Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199775286.001.0001.

Protevi, John (2009). “Beyond Autopoiesis: Inflections of Emergence and Politics in Francisco Varela”. In: Emergence and Embodiment: New Essays on Second-Order Systems Theory. Ed. by Bruce Clarke and Mark B. N. Hansen. Durham: Duke University Press Books, pp. 94–112. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1215/9780822391388.

Rödl, Sebastian (2007). Self-Consciousness. Harvard University Press.

Rosen, Gideon (1994). “Objectivity and Modern Idealism:What Is The Question?” In: Philosophy in Mind: The Place of Philosophy in the Study of Mind. Ed. by Michaelis Michael and John O’Leary-Hawthorne. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 277–319. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-1008-2_17.

Rosenberg, Alexander (2015). Philosophy of social science. 5th. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Roth, Abraham Sesshu (2004). “Shared Agency and Contralateral Commitments”. The

Philosophical Review 113(3), pp. 359–410. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-113-3-359.

Rouse, Joseph (2023). “Social Practices as Biological Niche Construction”. In: Chicago: University of Chicago Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226827964.001.0001.

Rust, Joshua (2022). “Precedent as a Path Laid down in Walking: Grounding Intrinsic Normativity in a History of Response”. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 23, pp. 435–466. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-022-09865-z.

Rust, Joshua (2023a). “Enactivist Social Ontology”. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09952-9.

Rust, Joshua (2023b). “Institutional Genidentity”. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 10(4), pp. 695–714. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2023.23.

Rust, Joshua (2024a). “Beginning at the Beginning: Predictive Processing and Coupled Representations”. Philosophical Psychology. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2024.2440037.

Rust, Joshua (2024b). “Globalization, Political Realism, and the Agent-Exclusion Problem”. In: Globalization, Cultural Diversity and Schooling. Globalisation, Comparative Education and Policy Research. Ed. by Joseph Zajda and S Majhanovich. Berlin: Springer, pp. 107–130. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-53219-1_6.

Rust, Joshua (2024c). “Minimal Agents in Natural and Artificial Systems”. In: Anna’s Ai Anthology. How to Live with Smart Machines? Ed. by Anna Strasser. Berlin: Xenomoi Verlag, pp. 93–122.

Schwitzgebel, Eric (2020). “Is There Something it’s Like to be a Garden Snail”. Philosophical Topics 48(1), pp. 39–63. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/philtopics20204813.

Searle, John R (1995). The Construction of Social Reality. New York: The Free Press.

Selznick, Philip (1948). “Foundations of the Theory of Organization”. American Sociological Review 13(1), pp. 25–35. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2086752.

Selznick, Philip (1949). TVA and the Grass Roots: A Study of Politics and Organization. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Selznick, Philip (1957). Leadership in Administration: A Sociological Interpretation. University of California Press.

Stapleton, Mog and Tom Froese (2015). “Is Collective Agency a Coherent Idea? Considerations from the Enactive Theory of Agency”. In: Collective Agency and Cooperation in Natural and Artificial Systems: Explanation, Implementation and Simulation. Ed. by Catrin Misselhorn. Philosophical Studies Series. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 219–236. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-15515-9_12.

Sterelny, Kim (2003). Thought in a Hostile World: The Evolution of Human Cognition. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.

Thomasson, Amie L (2019). “The Ontology of Social Groups”. Synthese 196(12), pp. 4829–4845. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1185-y.

Thompson, Evan (2007). Mind in Life. Harvard University Press.

Thompson, Evan (2022). “Could All Life Be Sentient?” Journal of Consciousness Studies 29(3–4), pp. 229–265. DOI: https://doi.org/10.53765/20512201.29.3.229.

Varela, Francisco J (1979). Principles of Biological Autonomy. New York: Elsevier North Holland. Wahlberg, Tobias Hansson (2020). “Causal Powers and Social Ontology”. Synthese 197(3),pp. 1357–1377. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1763-2.

Weber, Andreas and Francisco J Varela (2002). “Life after Kant: Natural Purposes and the Autopoietic Foundations of Biological Individuality”. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1(2), pp. 97–125. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1020368120174.

Weber, Max (1905). The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism: And Other Writings. Translated by Peter Baehr and Gordon C. Wells. New York: Penguin Classics.

Wright, L (1976). Teleological Explanations: An Etiological Analysis of Goals and Functions. University of California Press.

Zimmer, Carl (2008). Microcosm: E. Coli and the New Science of Life. Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.

Downloads

Published

2025-05-07

How to Cite

Rust, Joshua. 2025. “Minimal Group Agency: A Bio-Social Ontology”. Journal of Social Ontology 11 (1). Vienna, Austria:28-62. https://doi.org/10.25365/jso-2025-8918.

Issue

Section

Articles