The Relevance of Causal Social Construction
Keywords:
social construction, causal constructionism, constitutive constructionism, silencing, stereotype threatAbstract
Social constructionist claims are surprising and interesting when they entail that presumably natural kinds are in fact socially constructed. The claims are interesting because of their theoretical and political importance. Authors like Díaz-León argue that constitutive social construction is more relevant for achieving social justice than causal social construction. This paper challenges this claim. Assuming there are socially salient groups that are discriminated against, the paper presents a dilemma: if there were no constitutively constructed social kinds, the causes of the discrimination of existing social groups would have to be addressed, and understanding causal social construction would be relevant to achieve social justice. On the other hand, not all possible constitutively socially constructed kinds are actual social kinds. If an existing social group is constitutively constructed as a social kind K, the fact that it actually exists as a K has social causes. Again, causal social construction is relevant. The paper argues that (i) for any actual social kind X, if X is constitutively socially constructed as K, then it is also causally socially constructed; and (ii) causal social construction is at least as relevant as constitutive social construction for concerns of social justice. For illustration, I draw upon two phenomena that are presumed to contribute towards the discrimination of women: (i) the poor performance effects of stereotype threat, and (ii) the silencing effects of gendered language use.
References
Boyd, R. (1988): “How to be a Moral Realist”. In: Moral Realism. pp. 181–228. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Butler, J. (1990): Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. Oxford: Routledge.
Carlson, K. and J. Conard (2011): “The Last Name Effect: How Last Name Influences Acquisition Timing.” In: Journal of Consumer Research 38. No. 2, p. 300–307. https://doi.org/10.1086/658470
De Beauvoir, S. (1952): The Second Sex. New York: Vintage Books.
Dretske, F. (1988): Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Díaz-León, E. (2015): “What is Social Construction?” In: European Journal of Philosophy 23. No. 4, p. 1137–1152. https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12033
Fausto-Sterling, A. (2000): Sexing the Body. New York: Basic Books.
Fine, C. (2010): Delusions of Gender: How our Minds, Society and Neurosexism Create Difference. New York: W. W. Norton.
Fine, C. (2013): “New Insights into Gendered Brain Wiring, or a Perfect Case Study in Neurosexism?” The Conversation. http://theconversation.com/new-insights-into-gendered-brain-wiring-or-a-perfect-case-study-in-neurosexism-21083, Accessed 4 December 2013.
Finnigan, K. M. and K. S. Corker (2016): “Do Performance Avoidance Goals Moderate the Effect of Different types of Stereotype Threat on Women’s Math Performance?” In: Journal of Research in Personality 63, p. 36–43. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jrp.2016.05.009
Fricker, M. (2007): Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198237907.001.0001
Good, C., J. Aronson and J. Harder (2008): “Problems in the Pipeline: Stereotype Threat and Women’s Achievement in High-Level Math Courses”. In: Journal of Applied Developmental Psychology 29. No. 1, p. 17–28. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.appdev.2007. https://doi.org/10.004
Grünberg, A. (2014): “Saying and Doing: Speech Actions, Speech Acts and Related Events”. In: European Journal of Philosophy 22. No. 2, p. 173–199. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2011.00481.x
Gupta, P. (2016): “Do you Really not like Hillary Clinton, or are you just Sexist?” Cosmopolitan. http://www.cosmopolitan.com/politics/news/a52707/why-dont-young-people-like-hillary-clinton/, Accessed 10-February-2016.
Hacking, I. (1999): The Social Construction of What? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Haslanger, S. (2003): “Social Construction: The “Debunking” Project”. In: F. Schmitt (Ed.): Socializing Metaphysics, Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 301–325.
Haslanger, S. (2006): “What Good are our Intuitions? Philosophical Analysis and Social Kinds”. In: Aristotelian Society Supplementary 80. No. 1, p. 89–118. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8349.2006.00139.x
Haslanger, S. (2012): Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199892631.001.0001
Haslanger, S. (2016): “What is a structural explanation?” Philosophical Studies 173. No. 1, p. 113–130. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0434-5
Hornsby, J. (1994): “Illocution and its Significance”. In: S. L. Tsohatzidis (Ed.): Foundations of Speech Act Theory: Philosophical and Linguistic Perspectives, London: Routledge, p. 187–207.
Hornsby, J. and R. Langton (1998): “Free Speech and Illocution”. In: Legal Theory 4. No. 1, p. 21–37. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1352325200000902
Ingalhalikar, M., A. Smith, D. Parker, T. Satterthwaite, M. Elliott, K. Ruparel, H. Hakonarson, R. Gur, R. Gur and R. Verma (2014): “Sex Differences in the Structural Connectome of the Human Brain”. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 111. No. 2, p. 823–828. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1316909110
Kukla, R. (2014): “Performative Force, Convention, and Discursive Injustice”. In: Hypatia 29. No. 2, p. 440–457. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2012.01316.x
Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (2013): Born Free and Equal? A Philosophical Inquiry Into the Nature of Discrimination. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199796113.001.0001
Machiavelli, N. (2006): The Prince (EBook #1232 ed.). The Project Gutenberg. https://www.gutenberg.org/files/1232/1232-h/1232-h.htm, Accessed May 2016.
Mallon, R. (2007): “A Field Guide to Social Construction”. Philosophy Compass 2. No. 1, p. 93–108. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00051.x
Mallon, R. (2009): “Naturalistic Approaches to Social Construction”. In: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Maynard, J. and S. Benesch (2016): “Dangerous Speech and Dangerous Ideology: An Integrated Model for Monitoring and Prevention”. Genocide Studies and Prevention: an International Journal 9. No. 3, p. 1–27.
Noah, T. (2011): “Tyranny of the Alphabet”, Slate.http://www.slate.com/articles/business/the_customer/2011/01/tyranny_of_the_alphabet.html, Accessed 1 February 2016.
Saul, J. (2006): “Gender and Race”. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80. No. 1, p. 119–143. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8349.2006.00140.x
Steele, C. M. and J. Aronson (1995): “Stereotype Threat and the Intellectual Test Performance of African Americans”. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 69. No. 5, p. 797–811. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.69.5.797
Subtirelu, N. (2014a): “Beyond Bossy on our Gendered Characterizations of Leadership and Authority”. Linguistic Pulse. https://linguisticpulse.com/2014/05/19/beyond-bossy-more-on-our-gendered-characterizations-of-leadership-and-authority/, Accessed June 2014.
Subtirelu, N. (2014b): “No Really, Bossy is Gendered”. Linguistic Pulse. https://linguisticpulse.com/2014/03/28/no-really-bossy-is-gendered/, Accessed June 2014.
Sveinsdóttir, Á. (2013): “The Social Construction of Human Kinds”. Hypatia 28. No. 4, p. 716–732. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2012.01317.x
Sveinsdóttir, Á. (2015): “Social Construction”. Philosophy Compass 10. No. 12, p. 884–892. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12265
Downloads
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
License
Copyright (c) 2016 Teresa Marques
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 Unported License.